Wednesday, 18 September 2024

IDEA OF JUSTICE PREFACE

            1IDEA OF JUSTICE PREFACE



RECOGNIZING INJUSTICES

The book explores the deeply ingrained human sensitivity to injustice, starting with Pip's childhood experiences in Great Expectations. It highlights that the recognition of injustice is not limited to children; adults are equally driven by a strong sense of what is manifestly unjust. The key idea is that we are not necessarily motivated by a desire for a perfectly just world but by the urge to eliminate clear and correctable injustices. Historical examples like the French Revolution, Gandhi's fight against colonialism, and Martin Luther King's civil rights movement show how a sense of remediable injustice has driven transformative social change.


WHY DO WE NEED A THEORY OF JUSTICE

However, the the book raises an important philosophical question: is the mere identification and response to injustice enough, or do we need a theory of justice? The author argues that while diagnosing injustice is essential, it is not sufficient. A theory of justice provides a framework for understanding and addressing injustice systematically, rather than only reacting to it. It helps avoid arbitrary or inconsistent approaches to rectifying wrongs and offers a more comprehensive vision of what justice entails.


HOW TO RECOGNIZE INJUSTICE & ROLE OF REASONING

The book delves into the complexity of understanding and responding to the world, emphasizing that it is never a straightforward process of merely recording perceptions. Instead, understanding involves critical reasoning. Human emotions and perceptions, like the sense of injustice, can act as signals that guide our actions, but these signals require careful scrutiny. We must assess their reliability to avoid being misled by feelings or immediate impressions.

Adam Smith’s emphasis on moral sentiments illustrates this point: even though feelings can signal wrongdoing, they must undergo reasoned scrutiny to determine if they justify condemnation. A similar process is necessary when we praise others or things. This notion applies to ethical and political concepts such as justice and injustice, requiring not just feelings of right and wrong but also rational examination.


WAYS TO UNDERSTAND INJUSTICE


The author raises questions about what constitutes proper reasoning in assessing justice and injustice. It questions the objectivity of these assessments, asking if they demand impartiality, detachment from self-interest, and even the reassessment of deep-seated local attitudes and biases. The text suggests that reason and rationality are essential tools for discerning the demands of justice, and it highlights the need for a broader perspective that goes beyond personal or parochial views to achieve a more universal understanding.

The author  presents a theory of justice that focuses on practical reasoning and the pursuit of enhancing justice and eliminating injustice, rather than seeking to define or achieve a state of perfect justice. This approach differs from many prominent contemporary theories of justice, which often focus on imagining or characterizing perfectly just societies. Instead, the theory outlined here emphasizes the importance of comparative reasoning—how we can determine whether specific social changes or institutional arrangements reduce injustice.


Three main differences with conventional theories of justice are highlighted:


1. Practical Approach to Reducing Injustice: The theory emphasizes identifying ways to reduce injustice in the real world, rather than aiming for an abstract notion of perfect justice. The author argues that these two tasks—identifying perfect justice and determining what improves justice—are separate and analytically distinct, even though they may share motivational links.


2. Complexity of Comparative Justice: While some questions of justice can be resolved through reasoned arguments, the passage recognizes that there may be multiple, conflicting considerations of justice. Different individuals or groups, based on diverse experiences or cultural backgrounds, may reach divergent but reasonable conclusions about justice. These differences require reasoned argument and critical scrutiny.


3. Rational Discourse: The theory underscores the need for rational, reasoned argument both within oneself and in dialogue with others. This dialogue is essential for evaluating different claims to justice, especially when conflicting views exist. Through this process, a more comprehensive understanding of justice and injustice can emerge, even when perfect consensus is not achievable.


COMPERATIVE APPROACH


Ultimately, the theory advocates for a dynamic and comparative approach to justice, where practical reasoning, dialogue, and scrutiny are essential tools in striving to reduce injustice in society.


This passage emphasizes the complexity of justice by acknowledging that, while some comparative questions of justice can be successfully resolved through reasoned argument, there will be cases where conflicting considerations remain unresolved. It argues that there can be multiple valid reasons for justice, each able to withstand critical scrutiny, but leading to different conclusions. These competing arguments may arise from people with diverse experiences and traditions, within the same society, or even from the same individual.


DISENGAGED TOLERATION


The author  rejects the notion of "disengaged toleration," where conflicting viewpoints are passively accepted with the idea that each community or individual is right in their own way. Instead, it insists on the need for reasoned argument and impartial scrutiny in addressing conflicting claims. However, even the most rigorous critical examination may leave unresolved competing arguments, which do not disappear despite impartial scrutiny.


The key point is that the necessity for reasoning and scrutiny is not undermined by the existence of unresolved conflicts. Instead, the resulting plurality—where different priorities survive reasoned confrontation—is a product of thoughtful examination, not a result of avoiding or dismissing the complexity of the issues involved. This plurality is a natural outcome of the diverse nature of human experiences and perspectives.


BEHAVIOURAL APPROACH 

This author  highlights a crucial shift in the understanding of justice by focusing on actual behaviors rather than solely institutional frameworks. It argues that many instances of injustice are rooted in individual behavioral transgressions rather than structural shortcomings. For example, Pip’s memory of his coercive sister in *Great Expectations* reflects personal wrongdoing rather than an indictment of the family institution. Justice, in this view, relates directly to how people live their lives, not just to the institutions that surround them.

Contrary to many prominent theories of justice, which focus predominantly on the establishment of just institutions, this approach emphasizes that justice must also account for how individuals behave within these frameworks. The celebrated theory of John Rawls, which centers on "justice as fairness," focuses exclusively on the design of just institutions and assumes that behavior will comply with the proper functioning of these institutions. However, the current work critiques this focus, arguing that there are inadequacies in placing overwhelming emphasis on institutions while assuming compliant behavior. Instead, it suggests that the assessment of justice should focus on the actual lives people lead, which has far-reaching implications for the broader understanding of justice.

The shift from institutional justice to lived justice, as discussed here, impacts political and moral philosophy and is relevant to ongoing debates in law, economics, and politics. Furthermore, adopting a comparative perspective—beyond the limited framework of the social contract—can contribute meaningfully to understanding justice. Whether it is fighting oppression, such as slavery or the subjugation of women, protesting medical neglect in parts of Africa and Asia, or challenging the permissibility of torture, the pursuit of justice involves comparing and addressing real-world issues that affect human lives.

Even if agreed-upon reforms, like the abolition of apartheid, are successfully implemented, this approach acknowledges that we may never achieve perfect justice. Both practical concerns and theoretical reasoning point to the need for a radical rethinking of how we analyze justice, focusing on real-life conditions rather than solely on ideal institutions.

The book  discusses how the pursuit of justice is tied to the lived experiences and freedoms of individuals, rather than merely the institutions that govern them. However, it also acknowledges that institutions play an essential role in enhancing justice. The right institutions, along with individual and social behaviors, are crucial for enabling people to live lives they value and for ensuring that justice is achieved.

Institutions, in this context, have a dual role. First, they directly impact people's lives by shaping the opportunities and freedoms they have. Second, institutions play an important role in creating an environment where public scrutiny and discussion can take place. This includes ensuring freedom of speech, access to information, and the ability for citizens to engage in informed public discourse.

The passage also explores the concept of democracy, arguing that it should be understood through the lens of public reasoning. This means that democracy is not just about formal institutions like elections or legislative bodies but is fundamentally about encouraging and enabling discussion among citizens. This idea of democracy as "government by discussion" is influenced by thinkers like John Stuart Mill. According to this view, democracy's strength lies in how well it allows diverse voices to be heard and encourages reasoned debate.

The idea of democracy as public reasoning extends beyond national borders. At the global level, this approach to democracy does not necessarily require global institutions like a world government or global elections. Instead, it focuses on promoting public reasoning across borders, encouraging discussions and informed engagement between nations. By fostering public reasoning globally, the passage suggests that we can advance both global democracy and justice, making these goals more understandable and achievable.

In essence, this view of justice and democracy emphasizes the importance of public reasoning, informed discussion, and the role of institutions in supporting these processes, both locally and globally.


Broadening the Scope of Justice: Integrating Western and Non-Western Intellectual Traditions

The book  discusses the intellectual foundations of the author's approach to justice, emphasizing its roots in the European Enlightenment while also acknowledging that the analysis goes beyond Western intellectual traditions. The author aims to clarify two points to avoid misunderstanding.

First, although the book draws on reasoning explored during the European Enlightenment, this does not mean its intellectual background is exclusively European. In fact, one of the distinct features of the book is its inclusion of ideas from non-Western societies, especially Indian intellectual history. The author highlights the rich tradition of reasoned argument in India’s past and asserts that non-Western intellectual traditions, like those from India, have also produced rigorous arguments based on reason rather than faith or dogma. By focusing predominantly on Western literature, contemporary political philosophy and theories of justice have become somewhat narrow and limited in scope.

Second, the author rejects the notion of a strict divide between Western and Eastern (or non-Western) thinking on justice and morality. While there are differences in reasoning both within the West and the East, the idea that Western thought is fundamentally opposed to "quintessentially Eastern" priorities is a misconception. Instead, the author argues that similar ideas of justice, fairness, responsibility, and moral duty have emerged across different cultures and intellectual traditions worldwide. These non-Western perspectives have often been overlooked or marginalized in the dominant Western discourse, but they offer valuable insights that can expand and enrich global discussions of justice.

In essence, the author emphasizes the importance of considering both Western and non-Western intellectual traditions when discussing justice, broadening the scope of the debate beyond the parochial focus on Western thought that has often dominated the field.


NITI AND NYAYA


The author explains two different concepts of justice from early Indian jurisprudence—niti and nyaya—and how they relate to broader ideas of fairness and justice.

1. Niti  refers to the rules, laws, and systems in place to ensure things are done correctly. It focuses on the proper organization and correct behavior within society. Think of niti as the formal structure of justice, where the focus is on creating and following good rules.

2. Nyaya, on the other hand, is more concerned with the real-life outcomes. It focuses on what actually happens to people and how their lives turn out. Nyaya looks at the justice that emerges from these systems and asks whether people are truly able to lead good lives, regardless of whether the rules (niti) are being followed.

The distinction is important because a society might have excellent rules and laws (niti), but if people are still suffering or unable to live fulfilling lives, then justice (nyaya) is not fully achieved. Both concepts are important, but nyaya shifts the focus from simply following the rules to making sure that people are living well as a result.

UNDERSTANDING FROM ENLIGHENMENT ERA


The author describes two different approaches to thinking about justice during the Enlightenment period, a time of intellectual development in Europe. Here’s an easier breakdown:

1. First Approach: Perfect Social Arrangements (Social Contract Theory)\  

Some Enlightenment thinkers, like Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and Immanuel Kant, focused on defining the perfectly just society by figuring out the best possible institutions or rules that people should follow. Their ideas are based on a "social contract," where people agree to follow certain rules in exchange for benefits, like safety or rights. This approach focuses on creating ideal laws and institutions. A more modern philosopher, John Rawls, revived this thinking in his famous work "A Theory of Justice."


2. Second Approach: Real-Life Comparisons (Focus on Lives and Social Behavior)  

Other Enlightenment thinkers, like Adam Smith, Condorcet, Mary Wollstonecraft, Jeremy Bentham, Karl Marx, and John Stuart Mill, took a different approach. They were more interested in comparing how people’s real lives could be improved, not just by laws and institutions but also by how people **behave** and interact in society. This approach doesn’t only focus on perfect systems but looks at what **actually happens in people’s lives

3. Social Choice Theory 

This second approach led to a mathematical method called social choice theory, developed by Condorcet in the 18th century and further by Kenneth Arrow in the 20th century. This theory helps us compare different ways of organizing society to see which ones help people live better lives.


The Place of Reason


Despite differences between two Enlightenment traditions – one focused on social contracts (like Immanuel Kant’s ideas) and the other on comparing different societies – both share some key similarities. These include the importance of reasoning and the role of public discussion. Although this book mainly explores the second approach, it is still influenced by Kantian ideas, like how reasoning about the world is a key part of morality and humanity’s hope.


However, there is a debate about whether reasoning alone can form a reliable basis for justice. The first chapter of the book focuses on the role and limits of reasoning. I argue that emotions, psychology, and instincts cannot be used as independent sources of value without being evaluated by reasoning. However, emotions still matter because we have good reasons to consider them when judging justice and injustice in the world. There is no deep conflict between reason and emotion, and there are strong reasons to acknowledge the relevance of emotions.


A different criticism of relying on reasoning points out that unreason (irrational behavior) is very common in the world, and it is unrealistic to assume that people will always follow reason. Kwame Anthony Appiah, in his critique of my work, agrees that although reasoning is important, it cannot take us all the way because many people still act irrationally. This makes it harder for reason-based discussions to effectively address complex social issues, like identity politics.


However, this skepticism doesn’t mean we should abandon reason. Even if people act irrationally, it doesn’t mean we shouldn’t use reason when pursuing justice or social issues like identity. It’s also important to remember that what some may call ‘irrational’ is not always so, and reasoned discussions can include different viewpoints that may seem unreasonable to others.


Prejudices often arise from weak or flawed reasoning, rather than a complete lack of reasoning. Even people with extreme beliefs often have some form of reasoning, though it may be very basic or faulty. The presence of flawed reasoning is hopeful because it means we can confront bad reasoning with better reasoning. Thus, there is always a chance for reasoned engagement, though some may initially refuse to participate.


In this book, what matters is not the idea that reason is present in everyone’s thinking right now. We cannot assume that, and we don’t need to. The important point is to explore what reasoning would demand for justice, while acknowledging that there can be many reasonable positions. This approach allows for the reality that not everyone may be willing to engage in this kind of scrutiny. Even in a world full of irrationality, reasoning remains essential to understanding justice and may be particularly important in such a world.

1. The role of reason:

   Sen argues that reason is central to understanding justice, even in a world where unreason is common. He believes that even seemingly irrational beliefs often have some kind of reasoning behind them, albeit potentially flawed.


2. Engaging with different viewpoints:

   Sen suggests that we should try to understand and engage with different viewpoints through reasoned discussion. He acknowledges that what might appear as "unreason" to some might have its own logic.


3. The possibility of multiple valid perspectives:

   Sen argues that there isn't always a single correct answer. Multiple reasonable positions can coexist on complex issues.


4. The importance of critical examination:

   Even if not everyone is willing to critically examine their beliefs, Sen argues that it's still important to explore what reasoned thinking would conclude about justice.


5. Addressing skepticism about reason:

   Sen acknowledges criticisms that the world doesn't always follow reason. However, he argues this doesn't mean we shouldn't use reason as much as we can when thinking about justice.


6. Confronting bad reasoning:

   Sen suggests that many prejudices are based on poor reasoning rather than no reasoning at all. He believes that bad reasoning can be confronted with better reasoning.


7. The goal of reasoned discussion:

   The aim isn't to eliminate all alternatives except one, but to engage in open, impartial reasoning about justice.


In essence, Sen is arguing for the importance of reasoned discussion in understanding and pursuing justice, while acknowledging the complexities and challenges of doing so in the real world.​​​​​​​​​​​​​​​​


PLURAL GROUNDING


About two and a half months before the storming of the Bastille in Paris, which marked the start of the French Revolution, Edmund Burke, a famous political thinker and speaker, made a statement in the British Parliament on 5 May 1789. He said, “An event has happened, upon which it is difficult to speak, and impossible to be silent.” However, Burke wasn’t talking about the situation in France. Instead, he was referring to the impeachment of Warren Hastings, the leader of the British East India Company, which was beginning to establish British control over India after winning the Battle of Plassey in 1757.

Burke accused Hastings of breaking the "eternal laws of justice," which he believed could not go unchallenged. He suggested that some injustices are so obvious that we cannot stay silent about them, even if they are hard to fully express in words. Despite claiming it was difficult to speak, Burke made a powerful and detailed speech. He didn’t just criticize one action of Hastings, but many, and laid out several clear reasons why Hastings should be impeached and how British rule in India was developing in an unjust way.

In this passage, the writer is explaining that when Edmund Burke argued for the impeachment of Warren Hastings, he didn't rely on just one strong reason to prove his point. Instead, Burke used multiple different reasons to build his case. This method is called "plural grounding," where you use several arguments without worrying about which one is the strongest. The main question here is whether we need to agree on just one reason to agree that an injustice needs to be corrected. What's important is that we can feel strongly that something is unjust for various reasons, even if we don't all agree on which reason is the most important.

1. Timing: This event happened about two and a half months before the French Revolution began with the storming of the Bastille in Paris.

2. Edmund Burke: He was a political philosopher and speaker who gave a speech in the London Parliament on May 5, 1789.

3. Burke's quote: He said, "An event has happened, upon which it is difficult to speak, and impossible to be silent." This means something so important happened that it's hard to talk about, but you can't stay quiet either.

4. The event: Burke wasn't talking about the upcoming French Revolution. He was talking about the impeachment (formal accusation) of Warren Hastings.

5. Warren Hastings: He was the leader of the British East India Company, which was establishing British rule in India after winning a battle in 1757.

6. Burke's accusation: He said Hastings had broken "eternal laws of justice."

7. The meaning: Burke's statement about not being able to stay silent is often true when we see clear injustice. It makes us angry in a way that's hard to express.

8. Need for analysis: Even though injustice can be hard to talk about, we still need to clearly explain and carefully examine it.

9. Burke's speech: Despite saying it was hard to speak about, Burke actually spoke at length. He talked about many things Hastings had done wrong and gave several reasons why Hastings should be put on trial.

10. Broader context: Burke used this opportunity to criticize not just Hastings, but also the nature of British rule in India that was developing at that time.

11. Burke's approach: He didn't give just one main reason for impeaching Warren Hastings. Instead, he presented several different reasons.

12. Plural grounding: This is a term for using multiple different arguments to support a position, without trying to decide which argument is the most important.

13. The author's interest: The author (likely Amartya Sen) says he will explore this idea of "plural grounding" later in his book.

14. The key question: Do we need to agree on one specific reason for condemning something as unjust, in order to agree that it is indeed unjust and needs to be fixed urgently?

15. The author's perspective on justice: He believes that it's possible to strongly feel that something is unjust for many different reasons, without everyone agreeing on which reason is the most important.

16. Implications: This suggests that people can agree that an injustice exists and needs to be addressed, even if they have different reasons for believing so.

17. Relevance to justice: The author sees this idea as central to understanding justice - that agreement on the existence of injustice doesn't require agreement on the primary reason for that injustice.

In essence, the author is suggesting that we can recognize and agree on injustice without necessarily agreeing on why something is unjust. This idea of "plural grounding" allows for a more flexible and inclusive approach to identifying and addressing injustice.

"Congruent Implications in Evaluating Complex Decisions: The Iraq War Example"

This passage highlights the complexities involved in evaluating major decisions, particularly through the example of the 2003 US-led invasion of Iraq. The central argument is that diverse evaluative concerns can independently lead to the same conclusion, even if they stem from different premises or priorities.


Four distinct arguments are presented to critique the invasion:


1. **Global Agreement**: The decision to invade lacked the consensus and legitimacy that global cooperation, particularly through institutions like the United Nations, provides. Unilateral action of this kind undermines international law and cooperative decision-making.


2. **Informed Decision-making**: The invasion was based on flawed or incomplete information, such as the erroneous belief that Iraq possessed weapons of mass destruction (WMDs). Decisions of such magnitude, involving human lives, must be grounded in verified facts.


3. **Distortion of Democracy**: The manipulation and distortion of information presented to the public, such as false links between Saddam Hussein and 9/11, eroded democratic decision-making. A well-functioning democracy depends on informed citizens, and informational deception undermines this foundation.


4. **Consequences of Intervention**: The aftermath of the invasion—whether it would bring peace or increase global instability—was overlooked. In reality, the invasion exacerbated violence, terrorism, and instability in the Middle East.


Despite their differences, all these critiques converge on a single conclusion: the invasion was a grave mistake. The passage further argues that it is not necessary to prioritize one evaluative concern over another when all plausible arguments lead to the same outcome. Instead of reducing competing principles to one dominant criterion, recognizing the validity of multiple perspectives strengthens the robustness of the overall conclusion.


This reflection applies not just to the case of Iraq but also to broader inquiries within the theory of justice and practical reason. It encourages an inclusive approach to decision-making, allowing multiple evaluative concerns to coexist and inform judgments.


The author argues that while these criteria are based on different evaluative concerns, they all lead to the same conclusion: that the invasion of Iraq was a mistake. This convergence of diverse arguments towards a single conclusion demonstrates that it's not always necessary to prioritize or reduce multiple principles to a single criterion to reach a robust decision or evaluation.

The broader implication is that in complex decision-making processes, including matters of justice and practical reason, it's possible to arrive at meaningful conclusions without arbitrarily eliminating all but one evaluative principle. This approach allows for a more nuanced and comprehensive assessment of complex situations, acknowledging that multiple factors can be relevant and important simultaneously.

No comments:

Post a Comment